From painting to poetry to new media technologies, this book theorizes "the image" beyond the logic of representationalism and provokes new ways of engaging topics of embodiment, agency, history, and technology.
"Sinopsis" puede pertenecer a otra edición de este libro.
Jacques Khalip is Associate Professor of English and Modern Culture and Media at Brown University. He is the author of Anonymous Life: Romanticism and Dispossession (2009).
Robert Mitchell is Associate Professor of English at Duke University and author of Bioart and the Vitality of Media (2010).
Acknowledgments..................................................................................................................................viiContributors.....................................................................................................................................ixIntroduction: Release—(Non-)Origination—Concepts ROBERT MITCHELL AND JACQUES KHALIP.................................................11. "Self-Generated" Images PETER GEIMER.........................................................................................................272. Cézanne's Certitude JEAN-LUC MARION.....................................................................................................443. Nymphs GIORGIO AGAMBEN.......................................................................................................................604. From Fixed to Fluid: Material-Mental Images Between Neural Synchronization and Computational Mediation MARK B. N. HANSEN.....................835. When the Ear Dreams: Dolby Digital and the Imagination of Sound VIVIAN SOBCHACK..............................................................1126. Imaging Sound in New Media Art: Asia Acoustics, Distributed TIMOTHY MURRAY...................................................................1377. Three Theses on the Life-Image (Deleuze, Cinema, Bio-politics) CESARE CASARINO...............................................................1568. On Producing the Concept of the Image-Concept KENNETH SURIN..................................................................................1719. The Romantic Image of the Intentional Structure FOREST PYLE..................................................................................18110. Ur-ability: Force and Image from Kant to Benjamin KEVIN MCLAUGHLIN..........................................................................20411. The Tongue of the Eye: What "Art History" Means BERNARD STIEGLER............................................................................222Notes............................................................................................................................................237Index............................................................................................................................................281
PETER GEIMER Translated by Michael Powers
1. "Not by man's hand"
One normally encounters the term "self-generated images" [von selbst entstandene Bilder] in scare quotes. Such quotation marks are, as a rule, a means of establishing distance. One writes down a term and yet flanks it at the same time with quotation marks in order to make clear that a certain measure of precaution concerning the statement should be preserved. Quotation marks are insignia of inauthenticity, rhetorical separators, or—as Jacques Derrida formulated it—"speech act condoms, to protect our language from contamination." In the case of "self-generated images," the unreasonable demand from which the scare quotes protect us exists in the presumption that an image (or a plurality of images) without any identifiable causation could be generated of its own accord. The image that "generates itself" seems to be a monstrosity, a non-thing [Unding], if one assumes that people produce images; that is, that images do not come into being absent an intentional act but are rather the results of conscious or unconscious intentions. Here, in this essay, this term will also be handled less as an empirical statement or historical finding, and more—like the quotation marks that accompany it—as an indicator of a problem area in image theory.
In Homo Pictor, philosopher Hans Jonas contends that "[t]he external intention of the maker lives on as intrinsic 'intentionality' in the product—the intentionality of representation, which communicates itself to the beholder." This stream of intentionality is suspended in the case of self-generated images. The effects of an authorship that has become problematic take center stage whenever terms such as "automatically," "randomly," "naturally," or "self-generated" images are utilized: there, where a subject, a motif, a conscious or an unconscious intention is typically at work, a void emerges, and the need to elucidate this latter is provisionally occupied by the formula "self-generated." Who or what the possible cause may be remains undetermined at first—the only certainty being that no person was involved. In this respect, speaking of a "self-generated" image is, as a general rule, a negative discourse: it signifies who is not worth considering as the producer of the image, and marks first and foremost an absence.
In what follows, I will briefly discuss an early image-theological application of this concept, in order to then develop a more extensive examination of the "autonomy" of photographic image practice. The Byzantine image tradition is well acquainted with acheiropoietoi, images not made by hand. It has been said of these images that they either miraculously generated themselves or arose through mere contact (with the countenance of Christ). Here already there are indications of an interest in the conditions of origination surrounding images. The question is not (or at least not exclusively), what does the image in question make visible? but rather, first and foremost, in what manner did the visible materialize? Both aspects, visibility and visualization, are inseparably interconnected to one another. The observation or veneration of the image draws life from the knowledge concerning its special mode of production; more specifically, from the knowledge concerning how it purportedly did not originate, through manual intervention. As Georges Didi-Huberman writes, it deals with "traces of the divine," whose meaning rests upon "non-contact of humans."
No medium is more strongly implicated in this idea of automatism than photography. The first photographic images, produced in the 1830s, made use of this notion of self-generating images, here serving as a rather suggestive interpretive model: "[I]t is not the artist who makes the picture," noted William Henry Fox Talbot, the pioneer of photography, "but the picture which makes itself." Once again, emphasis is placed on the absent intervention of the hand; again, the void initiated by the unique methods of production is occupied by supernatural and miraculous figures. The visibility of the image is ultimately bound to the specifics of its visualization. Photography, writes Talbot, is a "little bit of magic realized—of natural magic.... A person unacquainted with the process, if told that nothing of all this was executed by the hand, must imagine that one has at one's call the genius of Aladdin's lamp."
Later variations on this theme show that such an understanding of photography should not be explained solely in historical terms, that is to say, as a consequence of interaction with a new medium that is still unusual and in need of explanation. According to Mary Ann Doane, the negative definition of photography was applied as early as Peirce's meditations on indexicality. As is well known, Peirce classified photographs under the "index" sign-type in his sign theory. Such signs stand in direct physical continuity with the object that they signify.
The index is reduced to its own singularity; it appears as a brute and opaque fact, wedded to contingency. In this way, Peirce theorizes the index as potentially outside the domain of human subjectivity and meaning.
In this respect, the photographic image is the perfect manifestation of the index. "In photography, for the first time, an aesthetic or spatial representation could be made by chance, by accident, without human control" (95). The following passage from André Bazin's meditations, "The Ontology of the Photographic Image" (1945), reads like a compressed, revised version of the thoughts already formulated by Talbot regarding photographic automatism:
For the first time an image of the world is formed automatically, without the creative intervention of man. The personality of the photographer enters into the proceedings only in his selection of the object to be photographed and by way of the purpose he has in mind. Although the final result may reflect something of his personality, this does not play the same role as is played by that of the painter. All the arts are based on the presence of man, only photography derives an advantage from his absence.
It is no coincidence that Bazin comes to speak in this context of the "the Holy Shroud of Turin," which "combines the features alike of relic and photograph" (8). The motif of the acheiropoietoi is invoked once again, this time in reference to the shroud preserved in Turin that allegedly contains the only authentic reproduction of Christ. Roland Barthes also considers photography to be "magic, not an art" and explicitly associates it with the image-theological tradition mentioned previously: "might we not say of it what the Byzantines said of the image of Christ which impregnated St. Veronica's napkin: that it was not made by the hand of man, acheiropoietos?" In contrast to the effect of the acheiropoietoi, the autonomy implicit in photography is now considered as a purely natural phenomenon. The Byzantine images employed miracles as the proof of their authenticity. "That made it desirable for images to declare themselves authentic by performing miracles, the classic proof of authenticity" (Likeness and Presence 47). There are no known comparable incidents in the case of photographic images. Indeed, the origin of images, their cause, and authorship were all equally questionable to the pioneers of photography, albeit in a somewhat different manner. At first it was widely held that they themselves (i.e., the pioneers) brought the images onto paper or glass with the help of a camera, light, and various chemicals. They selected the motif, decided the camera position, determined the exposure time, and so on. And yet, the distinction from other more traditional forms of creating images was inescapable. A glimmer of that "self" from "self-generating" always remains in the photograph, a portion that is neither predictable nor entirely under control.
Countless details can self-position themselves into an image simply by being on-site at the moment that a photograph is taken and are therefore—whether consciously or unconsciously—recorded alongside the rest. This is what Walter Benjamin refers to as a "spark of chance ... with which reality has, as it were, seared the character of the picture." Roland Barthes refers to this same occurrence as the "not intentional": "it does not necessarily attest to the photographer's art; it says only that the photographer was there, or else, still more simply, that he could not not photograph the partial object at the same time as the total object" (Camera Lucida 147). Much about a photograph is calculable, foreseeable, and leaves open the potential for formal intervention. However, there are also modes of photography that demand the unpredictable. A photograph is, from this perspective, also an occurrence [Vorfall]. Something in the image occurs [fällt vor], or something unintended seems to fall into [fällt ins] the image. In his essay "Photography—Being and Expression" Rudolf Arnheim describes the most extreme degree of this partial passivity—a photographer who snaps an image, without looking at what appears in the viewfinder of his camera. For Arnheim this action participates in the "uncanny":
What is uncanny about photography is that the picture comes into being the moment one presses, without previously having been involved in any way, the trigger on the little machine. Neither the hand nor the eye needs to do anything further. And since the part played by the apparatus seems so great, and that played by the human being so small, one hesitates to call such a product a "photograph," if by that one understands something created by humans.
Here Arnheim describes, as he himself adds, an "extreme case" of image production. But its probability or empirical frequency is of little concern for his argument, for even the unlikely case of a blind photographer "illustrates a property that belongs to all photographs." Arnheim points out that the photographer does not necessarily have to act consciously, see, or even be present at the moment of producing an image. It goes without saying that the creative interventions of the photographer are of deciding importance for an artistic assessment of photographic images; however, they do not represent a necessary prerequisite for the production of an image. The "part played by the apparatus" and the part played by the photographer complement one another, their respective emphases varying from case to case. That Arnheim refers in the same text to "machinations ... with which one falsifies photos at will by turning them into statements tinged with undeniable personal interest [in bestimmt gefärbte Aussagen]" makes clear that the emphasis on automatism does not necessarily include a theory of photographic objectivity (37). Like natural phenomena, the products of photography are by no means fraudulent, but when taken by themselves, they present no statement concerning that which is shown: "there is in photography always a certain opulence and contingency, just as there is in nature, for nature is not statement but being" (39).
Various authors and theorists of photography have developed different ways of filling in this void of the "self" in photography. Talbot's initial stance was that the image creates "itself." At another point in time he describes his house—portrayed in one of his first photographs, which he showed the members of the London Royal Society in 1839—as what he believes "to be the first that was ever yet known to have drawn its own picture." A role reversal seems to take place, as the object to be captured in the photograph places "itself" in the image. With this same notion in mind, Barthes refers to the "matter itself," to an "emanation of the referent" (Camera Lucida 80). Finally, Rudolf Arnheim cites the stake of the apparatus in the picture-making process and so accentuates the technical agency involved in making a photograph.
At least three different agents of the "self" were made responsible for the specific form of photographic image-making: the image itself, the photographic "matter itself," and the "apparatus" that mediates between the two. The discussion concerning this issue in the theory of photography during the last decades either categorically dismisses the "self" in "self-generated" or takes the form of an undecided meandering back and forth between these poles. The frequently encountered recourse to Peirce and his definition of the index has only further muddied the question. It seems extraordinarily difficult to arrive at a positive designation of photographic autonomy. As in the case of the acheiropoietoi, mostly negative definitions succeed: something in the image occurs and is obviously not made by hand. Against the negative determinations of photography one can doubtlessly object that they withdraw the medial aspects of photography from thought. Where one expects a positive explanation for the transfer of the object in the image, the negative explanations speak of unintentionality, unpredictability, and automatism. Moreover, Barthes's comparison with the non man-made images of Christ, Arnheim's appeal to the "uncanny" in photography, or Bazin's emphasis on their "irrational force" may in themselves already carry the features of a mythification or fetishization of the photographic image. So long as the negative determination does not suddenly change over into metaphysics or a search for an unexplainable being behind the technology, it remains a legitimate indication of the partial inaccessibility of photography.
The art historian Wolfgang Kemp has recently criticized this as a "falling back" on an "archaic view" that sought to downplay the role of the photographer. It is, however, by no means a matter of minimizing or denigrating the artistic and creative share in the image. That is to say, the "participation [Beteiligung] of the photographer" that Kemp mentions is not a static category. It varies according to author, intention, function, and method of image-capture. This is why Georges Didi-Huberman reminds us that a constructivist critique of photography runs the risk of "losing sight of photographic power itself, as well as the (problematic) point where the image touches the real." This point is, as Didi-Huberman adds, "problematic" because the insistence on the efficacy of the real can easily make it seem as though the insights, already acquired, into the aesthetic, epistemic, historical, or social dimension of all things produced should be revoked on behalf of a new ontology. For Didi-Huberman, it is a matter of opposing "another mainstream" and countering the "radical skepticism of postmodern discourse ... toward the image, even a photographic image" with a nuanced appreciation (70). In doing so he walks a thin line, which he indicates when he emphasizes that the photographic image touches [anrühren] the real (l'image touche au réel), instead of saying it contacts [berühren] the real. Thus photographic power does not allow one to grasp [erfassen] reality, but is rather an oscillation between the entry of the "real" into photography and the "formal procedures specific to this medium" that are resistant to further analysis. An image theory that attempts to encompass both technically created images as well as photographs just as equally must, in my opinion, contemplate both the "formal procedures" and "the real," that is, the intentionality of the producer, but also the partial unpredictability of that which cannot be produced.
(Continues...)
Excerpted from Releasing the Image Copyright © 2011 by Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. Excerpted by permission of STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
"Sobre este título" puede pertenecer a otra edición de este libro.
EUR 11,77 gastos de envío desde Reino Unido a España
Destinos, gastos y plazos de envíoEUR 4,71 gastos de envío desde Reino Unido a España
Destinos, gastos y plazos de envíoLibrería: THE SAINT BOOKSTORE, Southport, Reino Unido
Hardback. Condición: Good. Used copy in good condition - Usually dispatched within 3 working days. 999. Nº de ref. del artículo: D9780804761376
Cantidad disponible: 1 disponibles
Librería: Midtown Scholar Bookstore, Harrisburg, PA, Estados Unidos de America
Hardcover. Condición: Very Good. HARDCOVER Very Good - Crisp, clean, unread book with some shelfwear/edgewear, may have a remainder mark - NICE Standard-sized. Nº de ref. del artículo: M080476137XZ2
Cantidad disponible: 1 disponibles
Librería: Ria Christie Collections, Uxbridge, Reino Unido
Condición: New. In. Nº de ref. del artículo: ria9780804761376_new
Cantidad disponible: Más de 20 disponibles
Librería: moluna, Greven, Alemania
Condición: New. From painting to poetry to new media technologies, this book theorizes the image beyond the logic of representationalism and provokes new ways of engaging topics of embodiment, agency, history, and technology.Über den AutorrnrnJacques. Nº de ref. del artículo: 595015679
Cantidad disponible: Más de 20 disponibles
Librería: PBShop.store UK, Fairford, GLOS, Reino Unido
HRD. Condición: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Nº de ref. del artículo: FW-9780804761376
Cantidad disponible: 15 disponibles
Librería: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, Estados Unidos de America
Condición: New. Nº de ref. del artículo: 13178345-n
Cantidad disponible: Más de 20 disponibles
Librería: THE SAINT BOOKSTORE, Southport, Reino Unido
Hardback. Condición: New. New copy - Usually dispatched within 4 working days. 486. Nº de ref. del artículo: B9780804761376
Cantidad disponible: Más de 20 disponibles
Librería: Majestic Books, Hounslow, Reino Unido
Condición: New. pp. 304. Nº de ref. del artículo: 4270623
Cantidad disponible: 3 disponibles
Librería: GreatBookPricesUK, Woodford Green, Reino Unido
Condición: New. Nº de ref. del artículo: 13178345-n
Cantidad disponible: Más de 20 disponibles
Librería: Kennys Bookshop and Art Galleries Ltd., Galway, GY, Irlanda
Condición: New. 2011. 1st Edition. Hardcover. . . . . . Nº de ref. del artículo: V9780804761376
Cantidad disponible: 15 disponibles